Warrish Photography: The Good, The Bad, and the Ugly


Capitalism seems to be everywhere. The wealth accumulated by a so-called philanthropic economic super-class has spawned a new kind of political elite. Through contributions to political organizations, non-profits and disadvantaged individuals, along with the media attention that such “socially utilitarian” acts attract, members of the bourgeoisie have even become celebrities. But what still remains obfuscated to many – diverted, for the most part, by the derived “philanthropic” political elite – is the Capitalist’s effect on politics via civil society. Capitalism’s two main implications – the idea of supply and demand, described by Smith (1776) as the concept by which “the quantity brought to market is just sufficient to supply the effectual demand, and no more, the market price naturally comes,” and Consumerism, defined by Webster as “the promotion of the consumer's interests” – make clear the consumer’s inherent sovereignty over the manufacturer. This relationship manifests itself in the way by which civil society, specifically photography, influences politics. Sontag (2004) suggests that “photographs” are “‘surreal,’ a hectic euphemism behind which the disgraced notion of beauty cowered.” Specifically, as compared to artist-rendered pictures, “a gory battlescape…[that] is commonplace about images of war made by artists,” when in “war photographs,” seems insensitive “to find beaut[iful].” In spite of this moral dilemma, the consumer is ambivalent to war – unable to deny the beauty of camera-rendered battlescapes, yet reluctant to recant “war is hell” – and prescribes “what photographers ought or ought not to do...[the demand that] photographs that depict suffering shouldn't be beautiful, as captions shouldn't moralize." Despite Sontag’s implied pro-Capitalist, anti-Marxist ideological undertones, self-proclaimed Marxist John Berger in his Hiroshima agrees with the consumer’s demand and Sontag’s broad concept, “collective instruction,” but differs in reason: he repudiates the capitalist “original sin” that Sontag so champions.
Berger argues that audiences should not look at anything but that which is on the canvas. He suggests that beauty is irrelevant, that first hand experience “of the victims provokes a sense of outrage” and serves as the two-door gateway to empathy. First, through “a sense of horror and pity,” the audience attempts to feel what the victims felt. Second, “a self-defensive” declaration that “this should not happen again (here)” allows the audience to consummate empathy, to “bring it back home.” To avoid residing within the radical extremes, as in sympathy or apathy, Berger writes against the creation of a third-party, antagonizing comparative analysis. He “refrain[s] from giving the statistics,” arguing that they “tend to distract. We consider numbers instead of pain...we relativize instead of refusing.”
The item of most interest, above the binomial “yes” or “no,” is the reason why Berger believes images must be looked at for just what they are. He suggests that the effectiveness of emotion-triggering art is based on the nature of its consumers, their inherent goodness or evil. Berger concedes with the capitalist argument that the consumer is more powerful than the producer, confirming the existence of a “collective instruction.” “Is it inconceivable that the BBC would show these pictures?...I challenge them to do so.” What is this force that could challenge the BBC, but the very entity who gives it a face, the only force that controls its sponsors, the British government, the democracy?
But implicit in Berger’s acceptance of consumers’ sovereignty in a capitalist status quo is his denial of bourgeois supremacy, a denial of amajor Marxian critique of the capitalist status quo. Berger’s Marxism is pragmatic. He admits that, though the socialist revolution is a must, humanitarianism should never pay toll. Berger frowns upon “a Marxist…” who concludes her article “by evoking the likely scale of destruction, which would be caused by nuclear weapons” and assumably undermining the human experience because “the socialist revolution in the United States,” that would allegedly be the result of these nuclear attacks, would outweigh the human losses.
Even with a pragmatic view of Marxism, Berger still practices constraint. Berger argues against the capitalist conviction that man is inherently evil, the one that Sontag uses to substantiate the “collective instruction:” that beauty and explicit morality are of no need.
Sontag suggests that people are selfish and possess an internal dilemma, because of which they look down upon beautifully depicted images of war. She claims, referencing pictures criticizing America’s involvement in Vietnam, that “mainstream media are not in the business of making people feel queasy for which they are being mobilized much less than disseminating propaganda.” She quotes Leonardo da Vinci – “make the conquered and beaten pale, with brows raised and knit, and the skin above their brows furrowed with pain…make the dead partly or entirely covered with dust…” – but she still conforms to her argument. She suggests that pity and fear are two entities so much so that “pity, far from being the natural twin of fear…manages to swamp fear.”
While acknowledging a person’s innate self-interest, Berger suggests that people are good and look to sentimental pieces to understand trauma. He suggests images of pain should be considered solely on what they have to offer, regardless of beauty and verbalized morals, not because of consumers’ selfishness, but because of their innate ability to empathize. An “interest in these pictures cannot be an art-critical one...but after repeatedly looking at them…[the images] became a certainty. These were images of hell.” He suggests empathy for those in “the conditions of hell” is inherent in Man, but cannot be summoned by “list[ing] the sites, repeat[ing] the calculations” because “[we] know” these “facts [that] are in textbooks.” Empathy cannot be summoned through objective means because “originally” the meanings of these facts “was so clear…what these facts mean has now been torn out.”     
Sontag describes a demand – art should not be about beauty or explicit morals – set upon a civil society by its consumers and substantiates its existence with her conviction, that all men are evil. Berger agrees that a demand exists – supports it, even – but supplies an alternate reason for its existence: the reality of man’s nature lies beyond just the mythic “original sin.” Berger posits that man is inherently good. He concedes with the capitalist notion that Sontag brings forward – the consumer’s free will and the manufacture’s compliance is integral to the civil society. But Berger suggests that this demand is not a result of the selfish tendencies of the consumer to indulge his pity and “swamp” his fear, but to balance both in a mixed feeling of empathy. He claims that the producer is not selfish, but is the victim, wanting his trauma to never repeat itself. In this way, Berger’s article is a metaphor. He uses it to further his Marxist philosophy. Like any sort of victim, the proletariat must be understood by the bourgeois, the onlookers. He suggests that the socialist revolution will not be violent like the one Marx once predicted—rather, according to Berger, if the bourgeois empathize with the Proletariat, then there will be no reason to fight one another.